A paradox of ranked choice voting
In a multi-choice election,
ranked choice voting offers participants the ability to give a detailed account
of their preferences. However, there are
different ways to evaluate ranked voting results, which will provide different
outcomes. These different ways of
counting ranked votes are equally fair, assuming that each participant’s ballot
is counted by the same method. But in an
election in which certain options or candidates are polarizing (tending to be
at the top of a large group of voters’ rankings and at the bottom of the
rankings of another large group) and other options are compromise choices,
tending to be somewhere in the middle of most voters’ rankings, the way in
which these rankings are weighted in determining the outcome will effect the
result of the election.
Consider the following case,
in which four voters are choosing among four options (or candidates) A, B, C
and D. Each voter has made a different
choice from among the 24 possible ways to rank these four choices. Here are their votes:
|
1
|
2
|
3
|
4
|
1st
|
A
|
A
|
B
|
C
|
2nd
|
B
|
C
|
D
|
D
|
3rd
|
D
|
D
|
C
|
B
|
4th
|
C
|
B
|
A
|
A
|
In this case, A is the
polarizing option, D is the compromise option, and B and C have garnered
responses that are evenly distributed among the rankings. If we
assign 3 points to each 1st place ranking, 2 points to each 2nd
place ranking, 1 point to each 3rd place ranking and 0 points to 4th
place rankings, we find that all four options are tied, with 6 points each.
If, however, we give extra
weight (4 or more points) to each first ranking, the polarizing candidate will
win the election. Conversely, if we
weigh 4th place rankings more heavily, subtracting 1 or more points
for each 4th place vote while keeping the other rankings at 3, 2,
and 1 points respectively, the compromise option will prevail.
More generally, in choosing
among 4 options, only the relative weighting of the 1st and 4th
rankings will affect the outcome.
(Mathematically inclined readers can take a moment to confirm for
themselves that this is correct., and then consider what happens when the range
of options increases.) In our example above, there is no way to weight the
rankings such that candidates B and C will beat both A and D.
While we tend to think of
voting as an expression of preferences, of selecting a favorite among available
options, in practice our choices are often more crucially about avoiding the
worst options. How we decide to weight
the results of ranked voting may be as important as the voting itself for the
process of establishing and maintaining consensus.
No comments:
Post a Comment